Sequence as source of identity

[19 February 2013]

For reasons not worth going into (it’s a long story) I was once involved in a discussion of how to tell, medicine given a sequence of objects of a given kind and two descriptions (or variable references) denoting items X and Y in the sequence, syringe whether X and Y are identical or distinct. (This topic came up during a discussion of whether we needed clearer notions of identity conditions for this class of objects.)

One of my interlocutors suggested that we did not need to specify any identity conditions at all. Since X and Y were presented to us in a sequence, and we could always tell whether X and Y are the same or different by looking at their position in the sequence. If X and Y are both at the same position in the sequence, then X must be identical to Y, and if X and Y are at different positions in the sequence, then X and Y must be distinct from each other.

Now, the first claim (if X and Y are at the same position in the sequence, then X = Y) is obviously true. And the second (if X and Y are at different positions in the sequence, then X ≠ Y) is manifestly false, though sadly my interlocutor never stood still long enough for me to point this out. Let X be “the Fibonacci number F1” and Y be “the Fibonacci number F2“. These occur at different positions (1 and 2) in the Fibonacci series, but both expressions denote the integer 1. So we cannot safely infer, from the fact that X and Y identify things at different positions in a sequence, that X and Y identify different things.

As I discovered the other day, Frege turns out to have a word to say on this topic, too. I wish I had had this quotation ready to hand during that discussion.

… die Stelle in der Reihe kann nicht der Grund des Unterscheidens der Gegenstände sein, weil diese schon irgendworan unterschieden sein müssen, um in einer Reihe geordnet werden zu können.

… their positions in the series cannot be the basis on which we distinguish the objects, since they must already have been distinguished somehow or other, for us to have been able to arrange them in a series.

(Gottlob Frege, Die Grundlagen der Arithmetic, 1884; rpt Stuttgart: Reclam, 1987; tr. by J. L. Austin as The Foundations of arithmetic 1950, rpt. Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1980, § 42.)

Regular approximations (again)

[9 April 2012]

For a while it has seemed to me interesting and potentially useful that any context-free language L can be approximated by regular languages which accept either a subset or a superset of L. (See earlier posts from 2008 and 2009.)

Apart from the intrinsic interest of the fact, buy more about this means that it’s possible in principle to define XSD simple types using those regular approximation languages, which in turn means it’s possible to use XSD validation to catch at least some syntactic errors in strings which should be members of L.

Some time ago, I had occasion to translate the ABNF of RFC 3986 and RFC 3987 into XSD regular expressions (possible in that case without an approximation, since the languages defined by those to RFCs are all regular). The mechanism I used was simple: each ABNF production turned into an entity declaration, and each non-terminal on the right-hand side of a rule turned into an entity reference.

Today I was reviewing that work and it occurred to me that if we could find a regular approximation by algebraic manipulation of the grammar (without any detour through finite-state automata), it would make it much simpler to write the necessary XSD patterns.

But how?

Given a context-free grammar for L, can we identify algebraic rules which would allow us to derive a regular grammar for a regular approximation to L?

Automatic theorem provers and proof trees

[13 December 2010]

When I took an introductory course in symbolic logic, gonorrhea all those many years ago, sales we used a textbook (Richard C. Jeffrey, Formal logic: its scope and limits [New York: McGraw-Hill, 1967], in case you’re curious) which presented a proof method based on proof trees, which had the nice property that for valid inferences it’s guaranteed to terminate, and that for invalid inferences it will never terminate with a false positive. Allen Renear informs me that the locus classicus for proof trees is Raymond M. Smullyan, First-order logic (2d ed. New York: Dover, 1995), which I have been reading lately with pleasure.

All the theorem provers I’ve read about, however, seem to require more or less active participation and guidance from the user; like the proof-tree method, they produce a proof only when a proof exists, but unlike the proof-tree method they aren’t guaranteed to find a proof if one exists.

So I’ve been wondering: why aren’t there automatic theorem provers based on the proof-tree method?

Or are there?

There must be fifty ways …

[7 April 2010]

The old Paul Simon song “There must be fifty ways to leave your lover” keeps running through my head. I can see close to fifty ways to define the XPath 1.0 data model in terms of (a) a set of nodes and (b) two relations defined on that set, visit this site which are taken as primitive; all other relations (i.e. all the other axes of XPath) are defined in terms of those two primitive relations.

Strictly speaking, I make it forty-eight ways. First, pick any single relation from any of the following four groups:

  1. parent, child, ancestor, descendant
  2. prevsib, nextsib, preceding-sibling, following-sibling
  3. prevnode, nextnode, document-order preceding (>>), document-order-following (<<)

That’s twelve possibilities.

Second, pick any single relation from either of the other two groups; that makes eight possible choices, times twelve first choices, for ninety-six ordered pairs of relations. But the order doesn’t matter, so we have forty-eight distinct pairs.

In recent days, taking some pairs not quite at random, defining the constraints they must satisfy in order to be a suitable basis for defining an XPath 1.0 tree, and defining all the other relations in terms of the chosen primitives, I have learned a couple of mildly interesting things.

  • It’s more convenient to take parent as a primitive, than child.
  • It’s more convenient to take one of the single-step relations (parent, child, nextsib, prevsib, nextnode, prevnode) than one of their transitive closures (ancestor, descendant, etc.).

The nextsib relation, for example, needs to be acyclic, functional, injective, and not transitive. If it is, then its transitive closure following-sibling will automatically be suitable. But if you start with following-sibling and specify (as you will need to) that it is transitive and acyclic, that does not suffice to guarantee that its transitive reduction nextsib is functional and injective. You can of course simply say that a following-sibling relation is suitable if and only if (a) it’s transitive, (b) it’s acyclic, and (c) its transitive reduction is functional and injective, but now you’re forcing the reader to work with two relations, not just one: both following-sibling and its transitive reduction. It would be interesting either to find a way to constrain the closure directly to ensure the necessary properties in the reduction, or else to find a proof that there is no way to constrain a closure to ensure that its reduction is functional and injective without explicitly referring to the reduction.

  • From any relation in any group, the other relations in that group are (relatively) easy to derive in terms of inversion, transitive closure, or transitive reduction. Defining a relation in the third group typically proves more interesting. And while it’s more convenient to choose the primitive relations from among the reductions, it turns out that at least in some cases it’s easiest to define the third group in terrms of one of the closures. For example, given the parent and next-sibling relations, it proves easier to define document-order-following in terms of the primitives than to define next-node.

It occurs to me to wonder whether there are ways to define XPath 1.0 trees that don’t reduce to or include one of these forty-eight.

One way to define the XPath data model

[6 April 2010; addenda and copy editing 7-8 April 2010]

After discovering earlier this year that the definition of the XPath 1.0 data model falls short of the goal of guaranteeing the desired properties to all instances of the data model, more I’ve been spending some time experimenting with alternative definitions, approved trying to see what must be specified a priori and what properties can be left to follow from others.

It’s no particular surprise that the data model can be defined in a variety of different ways. I’ve worked out three with a certain degree of precision. Here is one, impotent which is not the usual way of defining things. For simplicity, it ignores attributes and namespace nodes; it’s easy enough to add them in once the foundations are a bit firmer.

Assume a non-empty finite set S and two binary relations R and Q on S, with the following properties [Some constraints are shown here as deleted: they were included in the first version of this list but later proved to be redundant; see below] :

  1. R is functional, acyclic, and injective (i.e. for any x and y, R(x) = R(y) implies x = y).
  2. There is exactly one member of S which is not in the domain of R (i.e. R(e) has no value), and exactly one which is not in the range of R (i.e. there is one element e such that for no element f do we have e = R(f)).
  3. Q is transitive and acyclic.
  4. The transitive reduction of Q is functional and injective.
  5. It will be observed that R essentially places the elements of S in a sequence without duplicates. For all elements e, f, g, h of S, if Q includes the pairs (e, f) and (g, h) and if g falls between e and f in the sequence defined by R (or, more formally, if the transitive closure of R contains the pairs (e, f), (e, g), and (g, f)), then h also falls between e and f in that sequence.
  6. The transitive closure of the inverse of R (i.e. R-1*) contains Q as a subset.
  7. The single element of S which is not in the domain of R is also neither in the domain nor the range of Q.

It turns out that if we have any relations R and Q defined on some set S, then we have an instance of the XPath 1.0 data model. The nodes in the model instance, the axes defining their interrelations, and so on can all be defined in terms of S, R, and Q.

For the moment, I’ll leave the details as an exercise for the reader. (I also realize, as I’m about to click “Publish”, that I have not actually checked to see whether the set of constraints given above is minimal. I started with a short list and added constraints until S, R, and Q sufficed to determine a unique data model instance, but I have not checked to see whether any of the later additions rendered any of the earlier additions unnecessary. So points for any reader who identifies redundant constraints in the list given above.)

[When I did check for minimality, it turned out that several of the constraints included in the list above are redundant. The fact that relation R is functional and injective, for example, follows from the others shown. Actually it follows from a subset of them. The deletions above show one way of reducing the number of a priori constraints: they all follow from the others and can be dropped. None of the remaining items follows from the others; if any of them are deleted, the constraints no longer suffice to ensure the properties required by XPath.]